Changes

Jump to navigation Jump to search
no edit summary
|Authors List=Hakob Barseghyan,
|Formulated Year=2015
|Prehistory=The question about the rejection of theories has been an important one throughout the history of science. Many philosophers of science have attempted to provide an answer for how scientific theories get rejected. Both rationalists and empiricists thought that theories can be rejected or disproved in an incontrovertible manner. Believing that there is an absolute method of science, they believed that theories are assessed by this method, and if they fail to satisfy the method’s requirements, they are conclusively rejected.[[CiteRef::Laudan (1970a)]] [[Immanuel Kant]] echoed their beliefs. He held that scientific theories (especially Newtonian mechanics) are synthetic a priori. As their knowledge is gained independently of experience but is nevertheless synthetic, theories can never be rejected as no empirical evidence can contradict them.[[CiteRef::Kant (1781)]]
 
The rejection of Newtonian theory by Einstein’s general relativity in 1919 led philosophers of science to reevaluate their notions of the status of scientific theories. The position of infallibilism of the earlier philosophers was replaced with fallibilism during the early 20th century. For example, logical positivists (or empiricists) of the '''Vienna Circle''' advanced a probabilistic understanding of theories based on inductive logic. [[CiteRef::Godfrey-Smith (2003)]] They argued that we cannot absolutely know whether a theory is true or false. Rather, they thought that empirical evidence is used as confirming or dis-confirming evidence for theories. A theory was thought to get rejected when it was confronted with a sufficiently great number of disconfirming instances, leading to a detrimental reduction in its probability.[[CiteRef::Laudan (1968a)]]
 
[[Karl Popper]] argued in [[Popper (1959)|''Logic of Scientific Discovery'']] in favor of '''falsification''', which is the idea that scientific theories are tested via attempts to refute them. If an experimental result fails to contradict the predictions of a theory, the theory remains accepted. However, if the results of an experiment contradict the theory, the theory is rejected. The more attempts of falsification a theory ‘survives,’ the greater the confidence we can have in the theory. But since Popper believed in fallibilism, no theory was absolutely certain, and would eventually be refuted. Like logical positivists, Popper posited that the process of falsification can be applied to individual theories.[[CiteRef::Popper (1959)]]
 
In his [[Kuhn (1962a)|''The Structure of Scientific Revolutions'']], [[Thomas Kuhn]] argued that science is conducted under paradigms, which can be defined as a set of related theories forming the ‘worldview’ of the scientific community. The paradigms were distinguished using ‘normal science’ and ‘scientific revolutions.’ Science conducted within a paradigm constituted normal science, while a scientific revolution characterized the transition from one paradigm to another. Most importantly, Kuhn believed that there is an accumulation of anomalies that theories often fail to explain. When there is a critical mass of anomalies that the theories within a given paradigm fail to explicate, a scientific revolution takes place that ushers in the era of a new paradigm whose theories provide sufficient explanations of anomalies. Crucially, the theories of the previous paradigm are rejected and replaced by those of the new paradigm. Hence, there is a whole-scale rejection of theories of one paradigm, which are replaced by those of the new one.[[CiteRef::Kuhn (1962a)]] Interestingly, Kuhn differs from logical positivist and Popper, because the former takes theory evaluation as a ‘holistic’ process, while the latter two thought that individual theories can be tested and, therefore, rejected. Another important difference between Kuhn and the earlier philosophers is his emphasis on the contingent scientific community as opposed to the tendencies of explicating the universal method of science.
 
Arguing in his [[Lakatos (1978a)|''Methodology of Scientific Research Programs'']], [[Imre Lakatos]] viewed theories not in isolation, but as part of an interrelated set that he named research programmes. A '''research programme''' is composed of the ‘hard core’ and the ‘protective belt.’ The former contains the central and fundamental theories of the programme, whereas the latter included subsidiary and secondary theories or assumptions. In light of the emergence of experimental anomalies or new data, Lakatos argued that the protective belt was modified to explain the new phenomenon, so that the hard core could be retained. Hence, it was theories in the protective belt that could be rejected and modified. Theories in the hard core were immune to rejection.[[CiteRef::Lakatos (1978a)]] Lakatos was influenced by Popper as he used his notions of theory falsification. However, like Kuhn, he utilized the Quine-Duhem thesis, especially the idea that theories are not tested in isolation, but as part of a web of beliefs. Accordingly, his views on theory rejection reflected the notion that, contrary to the views of most philosophers of early and mid 20th century, theories can only be evaluated as part of a system of beliefs.
 
Building on the ideas such of his predecessors, the later [[Larry Laudan]] proposed the reticulated model in his book. [[Laudan (1984a)|''Science and Values'']] '''Reticulated model''' posits that the values, methodologies, and theories of a given scientific community at a time mutually influence each other. It is through the interaction of epistemic values and scientific methodologies that theories are changed, modified or rejected. Therefore, for Laudan, the expectations of the contingent, historical scientific community and its methodologies lead to the rejection of theories.[[CiteRef::Laudan (1984a)]] Laudan’s ideas are arguably significant preludes to the foundations of scientonomy.
|Related Topics=Mechanism of Theory Acceptance,
|Page Status=Needs Editing
}}
{{Acceptance Record
editor
245

edits

Navigation menu